365bet

Philosophy of Charaka-samhita

by Asokan. G | 2008 | 88,742 words

Ayurveda, represented by Charaka and Sushruta, stands first among the sciences of Indian intellectual tradition. The Charaka-samhita, ascribed to the great celebrity Charaka, has got three strata. (1) The first stratum is the original work composed by Agnivesha, the foremost of the six disciples of Punarvasu Atreya. He accomplished the work by coll...

Go directly to: Footnotes.

Attribute (ṇa) [in Charaka philosophy]

The third among the categories enumerated in 䲹첹ṃh is designated by the Sanskrit term ṇa. Its categorial sense is attribute. Even though attribute is the preferred expression, the word quality is also intermittently employed, for it is in common usage.[1]

The word ṇa is mainly used in two senses: (1) strand and (2) attribute. One of the earliest books in which the word ṇa appears in a clear sense is the ղٳپīⲹsaṃhitā of ṛṣṇa-Yajurveda. There it means a strand.[2] The ṃkⲹ system of philosophy has almost retained the same sense.[3] Yāskā is the earliest known author to use the word ṇa in the sense of attribute, quality, and property. He says that sound is the ṇa of ś, and compared to ś, air posseses two ṇas including touch and so on.[4] ṇiԾ has also used the word ṇa in the sense of attribute.[5] ʲٲñᲹ, who gives a detailed account of the various meanings of the term ṇa, enumerates attributes even if it is not in a systematic order.[6]

Definition of Attribute (ṇa):

In the grammatical literature, it was ʲٲñᲹ to define ṇa first in the sense of attribute. He says that attribute is that which resides in substance, perishes, is found in different classes, is a super stratum, is not produced by action, and is distinct from substance.[7] At the same time, as a category, it was ṇād who was the first to give a comprehensive explanation of the characteristic features of attribute. He says that it subsists in substance; it is not endowed with a further quality, and it does not become an independent cause in conjunction and disjunction.[8] Further, it is stated that one attribute originates another attribute.[9] Different commentators interpret this ūٰ in different ways. Candrānanda is of opinion that the attribute like colour of the yarn produces colour of the cloth, for attributes of the yarn and the cloth are not the same. Śankaramiśra opines that the attribute of the final aggregates (Գٲ屹ⲹṇās), duality (dvitva), the separateness of duals (屹ṛt󲹰ٱ), priority, and postriority should be excluded from this characteristic of being originators.[10] Some others argue that this specification refers to those attributes that belong to the cause which produce attributes homogeneous to them, and it does not refer to all attributes. But, Srīdhara, who rejects this says that if a single attribute could not produce an attribute, conjunction produced by conjunction would become absurd.[11]

Caraka defines attribute as that which exists in substance by the relation of inherence (), which is devoid of action (Ծśṣṭ) and which becomes a cause (ṇa).[12] According to 䲹ṇi, the expression () has been included in the definition to exclude the all-pervading motionless substances like ś, for they never exist anywhere by the relation of inherence. The term Ծśṣṭ denotes one without motion as well as the one different from motion. So it serves to exclude motion as well as the finite substances (ūٲⲹ) which become the substrate of motion.[13]

The expression “being a cause� serves to exclude universal, particularity, and inherence, since they cannot become causes. Here it may be argued that the definition is unconvincing as it does not pervade all attributes like the dimension of the ubiquitous substances, and colour of the final aggregate substances for they cannot be causes.[14] So “being a cause� is partly unproved. Therefore its meaning should be to have universal which is invariable in the causes (屹ū貹ṇāv󾱳 峾Բ�) as it is a positive entity. This type of causality pervades all attributes and also excludes universal as they cannot have any further universal.[15]

Another explanation given by 䲹ṇi for being a cause (ṇa) is that all attributes other than the dimension of the ubiquitous substance and colour of the final aggregate substances are cognized. Hence the efficiency of being causes in the unseen cases is also to be admitted. Moreover the dimension of the ubiquitous substances can be the cause of the yogic perception, and so causality cannot be negated. Therefore, there is no chance of being partly unproved of the causality of quality. Even though such causality exists in universal, they are excluded by the expression . means a substratum () in which something exists by the relation of inherence and also means the contained () that resides in somewhere by the relation of inherence. So the ubiquitous substances that can only be the substrate in relation to inherence and the universal that can only be the “contained� of the same relation are excluded as attributes.[16]

The Mīmaṃsakās are of the opinion that one attribute can exist in another attribute.[17] But, both Caraka and ղśṣi첹 reject this. It is true that on certain occasions attributes are further ascribed to attributes like taste.[18] But, it should be understood that attributes are free of further attributes.[19] The attributes like conjunction which are often assigned to taste actually belong to their substrates.The ղśṣi첹 also express the same opinion in this matter.[20]

From the above description, it can be concluded that the definition of attribute given by Caraka is akin to that of ṇād. Even though the term which means that, it does not become an independent cause in conjunction and disjunction is not found in the definition of Caraka, the expression Ծśṣṭ serves the very same purpose with more perfection.[21]

Later on, Praśastapāda defines attribute thus: qualities like colour are those which are endowed with the universal attributeness (ṇatva), exists in substances, and are devoid of further attributes and motion.[22] For Sivāditya, attribute is that which possesses attributeness.[23] Again, it is said that being endowed with the universal it is devoid of motion and is not a substantial cause.[24] Keśavamiśra who expresses more or less the same idea, makes it clear that ṇa is only an efficient cause (a⾱ṇa).[25] Annabhaṃbhaṭṭa defines it thus: attribute is that which possesses universal and at the same time different from substances and motion, or it is that which possesses attributeness.[26] From the point of view of the Mīmāṃsakas, attribute is that which is distinct from motion, has subgenises and is excluded from the substantial causes (upādānaṇa).[27]

Footnotes and references:

[back to top]

[1]:

Attribute, quality, characteristics, and property are synonyms, See Websters Encyclpedic Unabridged Dictionay of the English Language, New York, p. 96, 1175. The term quality narrows down the scope of ṇa. “A quality denotes what a thing really is in some one respect; an attribute is what we conceive a thing to be in one respect; while attribute may, quality must express something of the real nature of that to which it is ascribed�. Standard Comprehensive International Dictionary, Illinois, 1973, p. 94. See also EIPK, Vol. II, p. 112; ENVC, pp. 132-133.

[2]:

yadhā guṇo ṇamanvasyati, evameva talloke lokamanvasyati, dhṛtyā, aśithilaṃbhāvāya. ղٳپīⲹ- Kṛśṇa-۲�-ṃh, with Mādhava's Vedārthaprakāśa, Bibliolitheca Indica, Asiatic Society of Bengal, Culcutta, 1899, VII, ii. 4. 2, Vol. VI, p. 247. ʲٲñᲹ also refer to the meaning of strand for ṇa.

[3]:

Loc, cit., F. Note, 59.

[4]:

śṇa� ś岹� ākāśādvāyurdviṇa� sparśena vāyorjyotistriṇa� ūṇa dzپṣa āpaśaturguṇ� rasenādbhya� ṛt󾱱ī 貹ñṇ� gandhena pṛthivyā� bhūtagrāmasthāvara-jaṇgamā�...� �ʲśṣṭ�, 2, Nirukta, p. 148.

[5]:

voto ṇavacanāt, Aṣṭādhyāyī-ūٰpāṭha of ṇiԾ., IV. i. 44; ٳٱ� dravⲹ� ⾱ṇa� tatraiva niveśite samavaiti ya� sa ṇa ityanvaya��. Դǰ on ibid., ٰīٲⲹⲹ첹ṇa, Vaiyākaraṇasiddhāntakaumudī of Bhaṭṭojidīkṣita.,Vol. I, p. 559.

[6]:

ṇaśabdo'ⲹ� 󱹲ٳ�. Astyeva sameṣvavayaveṣu vartate. tadyatha-dviguṇ� , triguṇ� rajjuriti........... asti saṃskāro vartate. tadyathā - saṃskṛtamanna� ṇavadityucyate. Vyākaraṇamahābhāṣya of ʲٲñᲹ., Vol. IV, V. i. 2, p. 299; �ke punarguṇāḥ? śabdasparśarūparasagandhā guṇ��, see also Ibid., p. 297. Ibid., Vol. II, I. ii. 3, pp. 98-99.

[7]:

satve niveśite'paiti pṛthagjātiṣu dṛśyate ⲹścākriyaśca so'sattvaprakṛtirṇa�. Vyākaraṇamahābhāṣya of ʲٲñᲹ., Vol. IV, IV. i. 2, p. 62.

[8]:

dravyāśrayyaṇavān saṃyogavibhāgeṣvaṇamanapekṣa iti ṇalakśaṇa�. Vaiśeṣikadarśana., I. i. 16.

[9]:

�.....guṇāśca guṇāntara��, Ibid., I. i. 10.

[10]:

See Śaṅkaramiśra on ibid., Vaiśeṣikopaskāra of Śaṅkaramiśra., p. 47.

[11]:

saṃyogasyaikasya saṃyogajanakatve guṇāśca guṇāntaramārabhanta iti ūٰvirodha�? na sūtrārthāparijñānāt guṇānāmapi.... tadaśrutavyākhyātṛṇā� prakṛṣṭadhīyāmeva nirvahati nāsmāka�, Nyāyakandali, Praśastapādabhāṣya., p. 352.

[12]:

samavāyī tu nśceśṭa� ṇa� ṇa�. CS, Su, I. 51.

[13]:

See 䲹ṇi on Ibid.

[14]:

This interpretation is in consonance with the Nyāya - Vaiśeṣika. վśٳ has pointed out that dimension of and ubiquitous substances, unperceivable universal and particularity as entities devoid of causality. (�aṇuparimāṇaṃtu na kasyāpi ṇa�.... eva� paramamahatparimāṇamatīndriyasāmānⲹ� viśeśāca bodhyā��.) NSMK, pp. 74 - 76. It has been pointed out by Śaṅkaramiśra that attributes of final aggregates are not causes. See Vaiśeṣikopaskāra of Śaṅkaramiśra., p. 47.

[15]:

See 䲹ṇi on CS, Su, I. 51.

[16]:

Ibid.

[17]:

Mānameyodaya of ⲹṇa., p. 268.

[18]:

For instance see CS, Su, XXVI. 73-79.

[19]:

guṇ� guaśrayā noktāstasmādrasaguṇān ṣa vidyādravyaguṇān karturabhiprāyā� pṛthagvidhā�. CS, Su, XXVI. 36.

[20]:

Գٲ� tat�, Vaiśeṣikadarśana., VII, ii. 4. 5. see also Śaṅkaramiśra on ibid., Vaiśeṣikopaskāra of Śaṅkaramiśra., pp. 400 - 401 ekārthasamavāyādeva tādṛśavyavahāropapattau guṇe guṅānaṅgīkārāt. TSA, p. 4. Thus, the idea implied in Caraka’s articulation recalls the expression "aṇa�' in ṇāds definition.

[21]:

ṇād had set the condition �saṃyogavibhāgeṣva-ṇamanapekṣa� to exclude motion which becomes an independent cause to conjunction and disjunction. For details see HSPCIC, Vol. II, 4, p.30. Similarly Carak has set the condition “one without motion� (Ծśśṭa) to exclude motion. See supra, p. 39.

[22]:

rūpādīnā� guṇānā� sarveṣāṃ guṇtvābhisaṃbandho dravyāśritatva� nirṇatva� niṣkriyatva�. Praśastapādabhāṣya., p. 227.

[23]:

ṇatvajātiyogī ṇa�, Saptapadārthi of Śivāditya., p. 48.

[24]:

jātimatve acalanātmakatve sati ⾱ṇarahitaśceti, ibid.

[25]:

峾Բⲹ a⾱ṇa� a貹Իٳ ṇa�, Tarkabhāṣa of Keśavamiśra.., p. 191. In the text, instead of a貹Իٳ it is printed 貹Իٳ. However it is a discrepancy.

[26]:

dravyakarmabhinnatve sati 峾Բⲹ ṇa� ṇatvajātimān vā. TSA, p. 5.

[27]:

karmaṇo vyatiriktatve satyāvāntarajātimān upādānatvanirmukto guṇo ṇavidā� ٲ�. Mānameyodaya of ⲹṇa., p. 244.

Let's grow together!

I humbly request your help to keep doing what I do best: provide the world with unbiased sources, definitions and images. Your donation direclty influences the quality and quantity of knowledge, wisdom and spiritual insight the world is exposed to.

Let's make the world a better place together!

Like what you read? Help to become even better: