Philosophy of Charaka-samhita
by Asokan. G | 2008 | 88,742 words
Ayurveda, represented by Charaka and Sushruta, stands first among the sciences of Indian intellectual tradition. The Charaka-samhita, ascribed to the great celebrity Charaka, has got three strata. (1) The first stratum is the original work composed by Agnivesha, the foremost of the six disciples of Punarvasu Atreya. He accomplished the work by coll...
Go directly to: Footnotes.
Dialectical terms (1): Debate (岹)
A debate (岹) is defined as an argumentative discussion with an opponent based on scriptures (śٰ).[1] It presupposes two opposite sides called disputants and opponents.
Debate is of two types:
Wrangling is the advancement of arguments in support of establishing one's own views. For instance, if the disputant puts forth an argument in support of his proposition that there is rebirth (punarjanma), the opponent then advances argument in favour of his proposition that there is no rebirth, which is antagonistic to the first. The inner motive behind such counter argument is nothing but victory. A wrangler always aims at victory. A cavil is just the opposite of this. It is a destructive criticism. It is a perverse debate. The person engaged in a cavil is not bothered about his point of view. On the contrary, he confines himself to demurring against the opponent.[2]
ṣa岹, in his ⲹ-ūٰ, does not consider wrangling and cavil as the two divisions of 岹. On the other hand, he considers discussion (岹), wrangle (jalpa), and a cavil (ٲṇḍ) as the three fold division of a debate. They are collectively known as katha.[3] 峦貹پś defines katha as a chain of arguments and refutations by many disputants and opponents.[4] The ⲹ-ūٰ defines discussion (岹) as presenting of two opposing views, setting forth ones own view in five membered syllogism, providing it by appeal to instruments of knowledge and to hypothetical reasoning (tarka), when correct conclusions are not thereby contradicted.[5]
The main characteristic feature of discussion is that it maintains a friendly spirit on either side. The aim of discussion is neither victory nor fame. Its aims is to ascertain the truth; the real nature of objects.[6] It is through discussion that one clarifies his old convictions and arrives at new insights. A wrangle is also a kind of discussion. But the difference is that it employs quibbles (cchala), futile rejoinders (پ), and processes worthy of points of defeat (ԾٳԲ) which are not employed in discussion (岹). They are employed because their main intention is victory.[7] Similarly, a cavil is a kind of wrangle in which an opponent attacks the disputant's thesis, but does not establish his tenet.[8] A caviller also makes use of quibbles, futile rejoinders, and points of defeat to refute the disputant. But he neither enunciates his thesis nor proves it by a reason. Even though wrangling and cavil are hostile in nature, they are justified on the ground that they may ward off attacks of skeptics, and protect the right doctrine like the thorny fence to guard the seed-beds.[9]
From the above details it can be conceded that the 岹 described in the ⲹ-ūٰ corresponds to the friendly discussion (Իⲹ ṃbṣa) of Caraka.[10] Similarly, jalpa and ٲṇḍ described in the ⲹ-ūٰ are hostile in nature and hence they can be identified with the jalpa and ٲṇḍ of the 䲹첹ṃh. But it should be noted that these two divisions subsumed under 岹 are hostile discussions. So 岹 and ṃbṣa can be considered as alternative names used in the 䲹첹ṃh. Thus, we can conclude that the ratiocinative procedure adopted in the 䲹첹ṃh and the ⲹ-ūٰ are fundamentally the same.[11]
Concept of syllogistic reasoning:
䲹첹ṃh is the earliest book which gives a comprehensive knowledge of syllogistic reasoning with all five members systematically arranged. Syllogism consists of
The procedure of establishing a thesis in debate by the subsequent four members of the syllogism is called ٳ貹Բ. Refutation and establishment of the antithesis by antagonistic members of syllogism is named پṣṭ貹Բ.
Footnotes and references:
[1]:
[2]:
Ibid.
[3]:
[4]:
tathā ca nānāpravaktṛka vicāraviṣayavākyasandṛbdhi� katheti sāmānyalalakṣaṇa�., ⲹ-Vārttikatātparyaṭīkā of Vācaspati Miśra., p. 313.
[5]:
pramānatarkasādhanopālaṃbha� siddhāntāviruddha� pañcāvayavopapanna� pakṣapratipakṣaprigraho 岹�. ⲹūٰ., I. ii. 1.
[6]:
tattvanirṇyabhala� 첹ٳviśeṣo 岹�, Sarva-ٲśԲ-ṃg of ⲹṇa-., p. 239.
[7]:
yathoktopapannaścchalaپԾٳԲsādhantopālambho Ჹ貹�. ⲹūٰ., I. ii. 2; ubhayasādhanavati vijigīṣu첹ٳ Ჹ貹�, Sarva-ٲśԲ-ṃg of ⲹṇa-., p. 239.
[8]:
sa pratipakṣasthāpanāhīno ٲṇḍ, ⲹūٰ., I. ii. 3; See also Vātsyāyana on ibid., ⲹ-ṣy of Vātsyāyana., p. 72.
[9]:
tattvadhyavasāyārtha� jalpavitaṇde bījaprarohaṇsaṃrakṣaṇārtha� kaṇṭakaśākhāvaraṇavat. ⲹūٰ., IV. ii. 50.
[10]:
“The former (Իⲹsaṃbhāṣ�) also called Գܱdzṃbṣ�, is known as 岹첹ٳ�. CHI, Vol. III. p. 563.
[11]:
Ibid.